Commentary on the paper "The contents of consciousness: a neuropsychological conjecture" by J.A. Gray, in: Brain and Behavioral Sciences. Transparent theory of consciousness: is there a problem? Wlodzislaw Duch Department of Computer Methods, UMK Grudziadzka 5, 87-100 Torun, Poland duch@phys.uni.torun.pl 1. Subicular comparator determines the content of consciousness because it is just a selective attention mechanism - to have a conscious experience one must pay attention. Gray falls into a common trap looking for "conscious components" in the brain processes and complains about difficulty of labeling neural processes as conscious or unconscious. Conscious experience is an experience. As all experiences it is a particular combination of brain and body states - reflective consciousness involves the concept of self but is not different in principle from the primary consciousness. Relaxation of the brain/body states, labeled as "conscious experience", is a subtle, nonlinear process based on the feedback to/from all sensory and motoric subsystems plus a feedback from those attractors of the brain's dynamics that are close to the final dynamical state representing the experience. Some of these relaxation processes, chosen by the selective attention mechanism, find their way to the episodic memory and form "the contents of consciousness". 2. Gray calls for a "transparent theory", not being satisfied with phenomenological correlations only. Without the concept of space-time, a highly abstract and metaphorical idea, physical theories could not be transparent. Transparent theory of mind requires precise definitions of mental events, mind states and their dynamics, and a space containing mind objects (Duch 1994). It allows to replace such statements as "that the informational equivalences ... are jointly instantiated into conscious experience..." (Gray, p.16/17) with statements that may be given precise mathematical meaning, such as "when the patterns of excitation of transcortical neural cell assemblies (TNCAs) reach stable attractor, binding together in episodic memory many modalities and features of internal representations into one mind object". Even if the brain receives information if such stable patterns are not formed (cf. the 'blindsight' cases or 'hide the thimble', Dennet 1991) conscious experience is not induced. A preliminary experimental evidence for the existence of TNCAs has been presented very recently (Pulvermueller et.al 1994). 3. The ultimate grounding of our conscious experiences is inseparable from the body (Johnson 1987). Mental events result from "frozen experiences", they are really past brain/body states remembered by the brain. The brain stores experiences (mind objects) and re-lives them, exploring them in episodic memory like an eye explores the scene by making saccadic movements. Since mind objects are entrained, sharing many features, there are expectations related to the next moment. The comparator model describes this process well but the essence of conscious experiences does not lie in the evolution from mind object to mind object. It lies rather in exploration of a single multimodal object: a thought, a sound, a color, each having many features and related to brain/body reactions in a non-linear way, leading to a particular relaxation of the organism, very individual and hence subjective. Bodily reactions in anxiety are not just symptoms but are essential part of this experience: symptoms and causes are not separable and body therapy may have strong psychological consequences. 4. Gray agrees that the content of consciousness is not directly based on sensory stimulation (cf. 5.7), as is especially clear in case of psychiatric disorders. Subicular comparator selects from many stable patterns of neural excitations (multiple drafts, Dennet 1991) that may potentially engage episodic memory. Thus (conscious) experience is restricted to mind objects activated by the sensory or by internal brain excitations, there is no direct conscious experience of reality. These mind objects are slowly formed during infant development and later "tuned" to reflect new experiences, The transient patterns change too quickly and carry too much noise to be biologically useful. In the real world recognition of objects must be fast, but learning may be slow (cf. long infant period), just as in the recurrent neural networks. This simple extension of Gray's ideas explains the puzzling experiments related to conscious perception, such as those disussed by Dennet (1991) (cf. also sections 5.2-5.7 of the target article). Long delays and strange subjective time ordering in Libet's experiments are due to the nonspecific form of low-level stimulation of the somatosensory cortex, resulting in long transition times to stable attractors of the TNCA excitations. If a whole series of confusing stimuli is presented then a stable attractor of the TNCA excitation may not be reached for one second or longer, each new stimulus forcing the system into a new pattern before the old becomes firmly established and episodic memory engaged. 5. The evolutionary advantage of consciousness lies in the ability to avoid unflexible behavior patterns (based mostly on genetic learning) that animals follow. Consciousness and intelligence, adaptation to complex environment, are inseparable. Conscious experience is nothing else but the reaction of the mind/body system, reaction very subtle in humans capable of having qualia (conscious experiences) associated with such abstract questions like "who am I"? 6. Summarizing: is there a problem in formulating transparent theory of consciousness? It is quite similar to Gray's theory: a) The structure of mind is based on subjective experiences - what else can be remembered but the states of brain/body? Conscious experience is a particular brain/body relaxation characteristic to complex minds. b) Conscious experiences allow for more flexible modification of behaviour and are necessary for intelligence. c) They arise from stable TNCA attractor states of brain/body dynamics coupled with the episodic memory. d) They alter the behaviour since various stable states share many features of internal representations and thus are basic to the way associations and predictions are formed. References Duch, W. (1994). A solution to fundamental problems of cognitive sciences, submitted to PSYCOLOQUY. Dennett, D.C. (1991) Consciousness explained (Little Brown, Boston) Johnson, M. (1987). The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Pulvermueller F, Preissl H, Eulitz C, Pantev C, Lutzenberger W, Elbert T and Birbaumer N. (1994) PSYCOLOQUY 5(48) brain-rhythms.1.pulvermueller